Skip to main content

On the Definition of the Concept of System

It took two hundred years for the concept of system to make its way into a science of its own. Curiously enough, if we compare Condillac’s [1798] definition[1] to that of Ackoff [1973],[2] we observe that the general understanding of the concept as a set of interrelated parts is basically the same, furthermore, if we filter out the different precisions made from a wide scope of ontoepistemological stand points, we might conclude that most definitions of system since Condillac share a common conceptual core that since the 1960’s has been formalized in set theoretic terms as:
S x {Vi | i I}       [Mesarovic, 1972]
Where “x” is a Cartesian product, “I” an index set, and V is a set of Vi relations. The concept of system grew before Condillac linked to epistemological intuitions in natural philosophy, as we can see en the works of Galileo[3] and Newton[4] in relation to astronomical order and the unity of that order. In this sense, we can trace its origins to the concepts of wholes and parts as treated by Plato in Parmenides or Aristotle in Metaphysiscs[5]. Nonetheless, following Buck [1956], we could postulate a valid objection to this basic core definition as an orderly relation of  whole and parts, since it is hard to think of anything which cannot be regarded as such, rendering the concept rather useless. However, the use of very general concepts is central to the epistemological strength of a science, as we see in the development of mathematics (with variable, function, set), physics (matter, transformation, order), or even in everyday language (thing, whole, part, situation).The fact that system is a peculiarly ample concept does not disqualify its epistemological validity, although it complicates its definition.
How can we maintain the generality of the concept and at the same time give a specific difference to characterize it?  Gaines [1979] found an ingenious solution emphasizing the human constructive aspect of the concept: A system is what is distinguished as a system.  This well known definition among systems scientists, defies traditional formal ones by the use of a double impredicativity. The obvious one is the apparition of the definiendum in the definiens, but there is also a meta-impredicativity, for a definition is a determination, and a determination is an action of distinction.
Definition
Definiendum
Definiens
System
What is defined as a system
System
What pertains to a definition of system

The definiens contains not only the definiendum but also the concept of definition rendering the elucidation apparently meaningless, and yet, in base to some uncritical common knowledge, to some everyday social communicative praxis, we can form a meaningful representation, for we understand that there are many objects that could fit into the concept. In fact, a further reflection upon Gaynes’ characterization shows the intention of his fuzzy definition: to provide a very general conceptual category to be used in a wide variety of intellectual scenarios.
In logical terms, a definition is the declaration that a certain newly-introduced combination of symbols is to mean the same as some other combination of which the meaning is already known [Whitehead & Russell. 1967,11], therefore, is a syntactical substitution which implies the extension of a semantical referent from one string of symbols to another. Although definitions are neither true nor false, and they do not introduce new semantic referents, the fact that some definitions imply new combinations of old referents may produce a semantical expansion. If I define p implies q in terms of the truth table of the disjunction ¬p v q, the semantical expansion is negligible. On the other hand, if a define subset as a pair formed by a set and an inclusion map under the condition that any two elements of such set are equal if and only if their inclusion maps are equal, the combination of concepts of the definiens expand with their synthesis the meanings of set, map, inclusion and equality of elements. Furthermore, it gives a procedure to construct a subset: the pairing of (S,i) and the condition to distinguish one element from another: for all x1 and x2 S, x1 = x2 i(x1) = i(x2). We tend to consider the definitions with null semantical expansion mere analytical substitutions, and think in terms of definitions when the semantical content is expanded and the definiens carries some extra information. For this reason, Gaines definition of system is somehow unsatisfactory: we expect semantical gaining from definitions, not only lack of impredicativity. Nonetheless, if we examine closer Gaynes’ explanation of his definition we notice that we can reformulate it like this: a system is whatever we chose to define as a system, or in other words, a system is the semantical action of establishing certain distinctions among objects, whether symbolical or sensorial. Of course, it would be absurd to identify any semantical action with the definition of system, for it would not give any specific property for the objects upon which we perform the distinctions. General speech is a semantical action but it does not necessarily determine per se the objects considered as systems.
Instead of looking for objects that might qualify as systems, maybe we should ask instead who makes the determinations of a system?, i.e., who declares a set of distinctions to be a system? With this procedure we would avoid ontological hypostases, like Luhman’s [1995,12] declaration that the concept of system refers to something that is in reality a system, or like Miller’s [1953] definition of system as a bounded region of space-time which contain parts associated in functional relationships, both postulating the existence of the concept beyond the anthropological action of the scientist. It cannot be proven that the semantical action and the choice of objects (the restrictions within the distinctions) are isomorphic to some non-human object, but they can be proven to be human actions. As Klir [1986] has expressed it, with system we are referring to a human action of abstraction distinguished on an object by an observer, and such determination reflects the interaction between the observer and the object. This definition is the line of Kant’s [2000,691]: a system is the unity of the manifold cognitions under one idea, a unity which has to be understood, under the epistemological framework of the First Critique, as equivalent to the unity based on one principle for the interconnections which constitute the cognitive action.
We could express the Kant-Klir definition in the following terms: a system is an ordered human cognitive construction of interconnections which have been determined according to a unifying principle. It is obvious that such a definition implies that the unifying principle is given by the choices of the corporate persona[6] of the scientist or the philosopher. But the unifying cognitive principle is far from being only conditioned by scientific deliberate choices related to a particular science, and we should include the cognitive conditioning of the human psycho-biological architecture as well as the social programs of investigation which underlie the first generalizations of science. Such generalizations are prerequisite conditions for the selection and ordering of material facts [Dewey. 1938] and they imply the choices of certain objects and relations from a much wider state space. It seems obvious to me that those choices are conditioned by homeostatic considerations of specific human groups, or in other words, that the objects and relations that get science started follow a principle of utility for the survival of a specific human group. The principle of survival utility, although based on the general conditions of homeostasis for biological organisms, contains a further symbolical dimension in human beings: the conditioning imposed by the acritical ontoepistemologies developed by a group, the Lebenswelt, which shape and modify the biological conditionings. Think for a moment about the conditionings that religions had imposed upon biological human forces, or how their acritical valuations shaped the ways of life of a community and the development of knowledge. In fact, the sociocultural conditionings expressed in the Lebenswelt may even affect the biological architecture of the genome, as the case of the adaptation to lactose proves [Damasio, 2012].
The world of the life of a historical community, the Lebenswelt (L) (in Habermas’ [2010] sense of the concept) is in a close connection with the realm of experience that today is under the scrutiny of life sciences. In the philosophical milieu, one is spontaneously drawn to consider such a realm exclusively under the scope of contemporary science, and therefore, systematically, but if we want to elucidate the concept of system, we should proceed more carefully, for the semantical actions which lead us to distinguish something as a system are conditioned by some automatic psycho-biological protocols which belong to a different realm, let us call it Unterlebenswelt (U). The acritical knowledge which constitute the communicative actions of L is the result of an evolutive process of communication and complexification which started beyond human grounds, in the communicative actions of U. Since communication is a social homeostatic tool, the basic semantics of L are predetermined in the emotional protocols[7] of U which enable the acritical character of the linguistic actions of L. In this sense, L and U define a socio-biological space without which the choices and distinctions which make something to be a system could never be understood. L-U, considered as symbolic actions of homeostatic valuation, are not only the conditions for the formalized symbolic constructions of science, but they are as well the linguistic core of social identity which renders scientific activity meaningful. Nonetheless, the formalized symbolic constructions of science are in turn conditions for those very same choices of the socio-biological space of L-U, in fact, we are talking of a three dimensional space U-L-Ü (calling Überlebenswelt the formalized linguistic constructions of science) for the constitution of the unifying cognitive principle from which we construct the concept of system.
In this sense, an exclusively mathematical characterization of the concept of system seems insufficient and the definitions carry some serious ontoepistemological problems that can heavily weigh upon the praxis of systems science. Let us take the current definition that most system scientists would approve, and say that S is a general system if it consists of an ordered pair of sets (M,R), where  M is the set of objects of S and R the set of some relations among those objects [Lin, 2002]. From a constructivist point of view both M and R are problematic concepts. Any theorem that uses the axiom of choice (present in the ZFC list of axioms) is questionable, for such an axiom is equivalent to a principle of omniscience, like Bishop [2012] correctly remarked. But our list of troubles does not end here. As it is well known since Russell, relations can be paradoxical:
(x)(y) (<x,y> z Pxy), for Pxy an open sentence on ‘x’ and ‘y’    (1)
Now substitute in (1) ‘Pxy’ for ‘<x,y> z’, then we have Russell’s paradox.
Furthermore, if we are to define relations as ordered pairs, we would need the axiom of choice to declare that every set can be well ordered and construct our relation. But even if we admit the axiom of choice, we can construct systems out of well defined numerical sets which, although related through the composition of a Cartesian product, have no computable relation, like the case of the position and the velocity of a particle in a 𝔖 quantum physical system (due to Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle). Set and relation are not independent concepts. How can we construct a set without the concepts of a relation of equality among its elements and a membership relation? And how can we construct a relation without the previous concept of set? How are we to consider their dependence? These problems are not solved either by the construction of the concepts of set and relation from the calculus of predicate logic. Modern mathematics, whether Platonist, formalist or constructivist cannot do without the concepts of set or relation, but the grounds for these concepts is not to be found in what we consider the practice of the mathematical science. In fact, such concepts seem to be developments of basic intuitions of our cognitive processes as proposed by Dehaene [2011], intuitions that were complexified  through progressive historical developments of the human thinking, as we see in the intuitive set theory of the totemic thinking, or in the Babylonian science of lists [Munoz, 2013].
An exclusively mathematical definition of the concept of system can only be done at the prize of meaningless constructions, rendered meaningful only through the praxis of social communication, i.e., when they are subsumed under a Lebenswelt interpretation of the concept of system, but not from the grounds which purportedly sustain it formally. Since systems are linguistic objects, they are conditioned by Tarki’s [1983] semantical theorem, therefore, the semantical image of a system, i.e., its concepts of meaning, definition, truth, and the like, cannot be produced exclusively with the elements of that system. According to the theorem, to define a formalized linguistic system we need two linguistic morpho-syntactical systems of different order, the object language and the metalanguage. However, it is interesting to notice that any composition of semantical concepts in the metalanguage asks for a further elucidation in an extra-meta-language, as we see with the aforementioned restriction of the concept of system to Tarski’s theorem, for the theorem, which gives the conditions of a semantical distinction (true-false, etc.) requires the concept of system, but system requires in turn the concept of semantical distinction. And something similar happens with the concept of definition which we use as a tool to represent the concept of system, for the concept of definition, as used in logic and formal reasoning, i.e. in Ü, is already a system with two objects (definiendum and definiens) and an isomorphism.
Any formalized definition or restriction of the concept of general system meets the syntactico-semantical incongruence of a Gödelian language (any language with the axioms of Principia Mathematica plus the Peano axioms). Semantic actions can be formalized bounding the universe of discourse with a limit or limen which is never absolute and never grounded on Ü. The objects of a general system are symbols, and therefore, objects under an interpretation, particularly the valuation performed by a specific philosophical or scientific historical community which lives under the constrains of a particular U-L-Ü symbolic configuration. For that reason, Klir’s [1991 ]concept of general system as an interpretation-free system chosen to represent a particular equivalence class of isomorphic systems, has to be considered in the context of the practice of systems science but not from a theoretical point of view. The different systems of the sciences, physical, biological, social, etc., are some sort of models of the concept of general system, but this latter concept is not interpretation-free, but bounded to epistemological restrictions (social and psycho-biological). Particular systems are under two types of interpretation: one is their modelization of M and R of the system, and the other is the U-L-Ü interpretation which share with general systems. In order to avoid the theoretical entanglement of the foundations of mathematics, we should need an intuitive framework for the characterization of the concept of system.
The wide scope of systems science does not necessarily have to follow the only way of mathematics. Furthermore, it could not accomplish its goals based only on a mathematical approach. The concern for a thoughtless misuse of mathematics in scientific practice (especially among social sciences) was already expressed by Bishop [1975] who asked for a more meaningful application of the mathematical conceptual tools. The epistemological objections presented in this paper to the current definitions of system do not intend to reject mathematical thinking (that would be impossible, for the basic intuitions of mathematics are biologically conditioned), but simply its implementation with judgment, i.e., with self-criticism and meta-theoretical tools. I do not think that the idea of an exact philosophy, as Bunge [1977] pretends for system science, could be sustained outside a naive Platonist ontoepistemology, in fact the computational character of the praxis of systems science seem to favor finite and constructive processes. But I think that systems science, if it wants to become the science of sciences, or put in a less Biblical fashion, the ground for contemporary epistemology, could benefit from a philosophical thinking oriented to the questions of meaning in the human symbolic constructions. The proposal of a U-L-Ü framework as a conceptual referent for the unification of cognitive principles which may help to the understanding of the concept of general system is grounded in the different types of human linguistic actions, starting from the emotional protocols shared with mammals, which give the semantic bases for human social homeostasis, and ranging all the way to the most complex symbolical human constructions.



Reference List

Aristotle [1995]. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton University Press. Princeton (N.J.)
Bishop, Errett. [1975]. Crisis in Contemporary Mathematics. Historia Mathematica, 2, 507-517.
Bishop, Errett.  [2012] Foundations of Constructive Analysis. Ishi Press International. New York and Tokio.
Bunge, Mario. [1977] Challenge to the Classical Philosophies of Science. Int. J. System 4, 29.
Condillac, Etienne Bonnot de. [1798] Traité des Systemes. Ch. Houel, Imprimeur. Paris. Web Edition: Bibliothèque Paul-Émile-Boulet de l'Université du Québec à Chicoutimi.
Damasio, Antonio. [2012] Self Comes to Mind. First Vintage Book Edition. New York.
Dehaene, Stanislas. [2011] The Number Sense. Oxford Univeristy Press. New York.
Dewey, John.[1938] Logic, the Theory of Inquiry. Henry Holt. New York.
Gaines, Brian. [1979] General Systems Research: Quo Vadis? General Systems Yearbook, 24; 1-9.
Kant, Immanuel. [2000] Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge (U.K.) and New York.
Klir, George J. [1986] Reconstructability Analysis: An Offspring of Ashby’s Constraint Analysis. Systems Research, 3, 267.
Klir, George J. [1991] Facets of Systems Science. Plenum Press. New York and London.
Lin, Yi. [2002] General Systems Theory: A Mathematical Approach. Kluwer Academic Publishers. New York.
Luhman, Niklas. [1995] Social Systems. Stanford University Press. Stanford California.
Munoz, Oscar E. [2013]. Mitopoética: la construcción simbólica de la identidad humana. Mandala Ediciones. Madrid.
Panksepp, Jaak, [1998] Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions. Oxford University Press. New York.
Plato[1989]. The Collected Dialogues. Princeton University Press. Princeton (N.J.)
Tarski, Alfred. [1983] Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Trans. J.H. Woodger. Hackett Publishing Company. Indianapolis, IN.
Whitehead, Alfred N., and Russell, Bertrand. [1967] Principia Mathematica. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge (U.K.) and New York.





[1] A system is nothing but the disposition of the different parts of an art or a science in such an order that the parts sustain reciprocally each other, and the last ones are explained by the first ones. [Condillac, 1798].
[2] For Ackoff a system is a set of interrelated elements with 3 properties: each part has an effect on the set as a whole, each part depends at least on another part and cannot have an independent effect on the whole, and finally, every possible subgroup of elements has the two previous properties. [Ackoff, 1973].
[3] Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems (1632).
[4] De Mundi Systemate (Book 3 of Principia Mathematica).
[5] In Book V.26. Also in Topics. VI.12. and in Physics. II.3.
[6] I have treated the concept of corporate persona somewhere else. [Munoz, 2013]
[7] As treated by affective neuroscience. See Panksepp’s [1998] notion of neural emotional systems.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Limen et Continuum

  Existence is Encounter. Meeting at the limen. In the limen, the masks disappear, that is, the basic intuitions of identities, such as the identity that I feel and think in relation to the tree that I see in front of me. The identity of the tree is a projection of mine: the unity of my process of perceiving the tree generates a mask in me, the ghost of a limited unity separated from everything else. The simplest form of intuitive understanding of masks and limen is given to us by numbers. Numbers intuitively express the liminal tension that is Existence. A little etymological note. Rythmos in Greek means flow. Arythmos (number) is what does not flow, what remains solidified. Numbers express the liminoid, and flow, rhythm, expresses the liminal. A rhythm becomes liminoid when we can trace patterns in it, that is, when we can construct masks of identities. Mathematics has spoken of flow using the Latin word “continuum”, the continuous. All modern science, since Leibniz an

An Epistemological Perspective of Individuation

For the ancient Romans, "Terminus" was the god of boundaries, represented as large stones used to divide and delimit fields. Festivals were held, called Terminalia, in which the stones that "generated" human space were sanctified. Our word "term" is the heir of that god, or better, it is that god incorporated into an everyday space, in our Lebenswelt or world of life. A philosophical term, whatever its semantic content, is the conceptual mark that we make by establishing a referential sign, it is the action of determining, of generating a reference in a mental space, a reference with which we make a sign correspond, or if we deal with a physical space, the correspondence with an object, be it a milestone, a stone, or an indicator sign. Since its beginnings, philosophy has used binary semantic terms as thinking tools, something that analytical psychology has also made good use of. One of the longest-running binary semantic terms for psychology

Trabajar con sentido

  Mi abuelo paterno, ciclista amater por la montañas de Ávila, soldado en la Guerra de Marruecos, después mecánico de locomotoras de Renfe y siempre un hombre bueno en el mejor sentido de la palabra, trabajó 12 horas al día toda su vida, librando un domingo de cada dos, hasta que la gangrena le deboró una pierna y tres dedos del pie de la otra. Su salario apenas sirvió para dar de comer a su familia lo que hizo que mi abuela tuviera que regentar una tienda de ultramarinos en la Calle de la Toledana, tienda adjunta a la casa en la que pasé mágicas temporadas de mis vacaciones infantiles, días fabulosos que me reviven con su recuerdo, las horas en las que disfruté de su compañia con la veneración del niño que se siente en presencia de un héroe legendario y amoroso. Estas líneas son en su memoria. Cada generación se yergue sobre los hombres y mujeres de las generaciones previas, sobre hombros de gigantes sin duda alguna, aquellos benignos titanes que nos han permitido tomar aire, mirar al