The
survival of the human group precedes in evolutionary terms any other symbolic
action, which will always have to assume such a survival as a fundamental final
referent. If the content of the organism’s categorizations are the successful
processes of adaptation, the valuation referents would be such processes, and
the meaning of all other actions would be derived after these. For this reason,
basic emotions provide the fundamental semantics of our language, and are
cognitive processes that evolutionarily precede what philosophy has called
rationality. Both the system of seeking and that of fear perform cognitive
functions of induction, after pattern recognition, based on the memory of
experiences, which are selectively strengthened by fear.[1]
Fear functions as a social regulator when it is coupled with rage, as can be
observed in the hierarchical formations of animal communities as well as in the
repression that the law in human communities entails. On the other hand, rage
communicates states of frustration in which individual instabilities that
affect the group are expressed, some homeostatic loses that are regulated by
means of the violent repression of unwanted behaviors. Likewise, the impulse for
seeking, from which an individual organism benefits, also occurs at a
collective level, and prospers according to its degree of symbolization, in
fact reaching its maximum power when it is accomplished by the group, due to
the concurrence of greater energies and to the multiplying effect of the
ordering structures which allow specialization. For its part, sex establishes
basic human relationships of association that structure the group, besides
offering epistemological analogies for the general processes of generation, a
strategy which has served (even today it serves at the core of some of the
great religions) for a simple ordering of the universe. The emotion of
maternity embraces the entire initial process of social learning, and serves
epistemologically, like sex, to elaborate primitive cognitive schemas in which
the universe is understood through a maternal or paternal link with it. The
social emotion is mainly communicative, and therefore cognitive; in fact, it is
this emotion the one which (modified by the others) makes relevant the semantic
content that is being transmitted, i.e. the group is the final referent of
meaning. For its part, the ludic emotion has at the same time a cognitive and a
social dimension, strengthening the bonds of the group. Play, by enclosing the
vital experience and self-containing its actions, allows the creation of
simulacra in which the actions of direct relevance for survival can be
anticipated and rehearsed. To sum up, all the emotions have a cognitive function,
and by having evolved from the relationships between the live organism and the
environment allow a flexible and adaptive behavior that we have called
intelligent.
According
to the model of Neural Darwinism, the global mappings generated perceptual
categorizations -or of first order- and conceptual categorizations -or of
second order- in which the frequency of certain actions which successfully
related the organism with the environment produced permanent circuits or
memorizations (understood as re-categorizations), that conditioned the future
behavior of the organism. Such categorizations imply a first type of valuation
which follow an inertial impulse for the preservation of life, to which we can
hardly call intentional or conscious, but which, nonetheless, generates a frame
of reference for basically syntactic processes that can be considered like a
proto-semantic system. These circuits –analogous in all mammals- to the extent
that they systematize pairs of internal and external stimuli with motor
responses, index representational scenarios from the categorical valuations, a
process of valuation of second order which takes as objects the global
categorizations linked to their scenarios, in which it is configured a rudimentary,
diffused, consciousness, that is linked to the emotional protocols, and it is
active insofar as these are active as well. There is primary consciousness as
long as there is emotion, and such a consciousness is nothing more than its
protocol of action. This second order valuation is the basic emotional
valuation that serves as semantic referent for the actions of survival, and it
is more complex depending on the type of perceptual and conceptual categorizations
that may enter in the determinations of the emotional neural circuits. To the
extent that the different neural systems, with their different tempos, interact
amongst each other, processes of anticipation and delay will be produced, to
which we could call of deferred valuation,
in which the protocols of respond become more flexible, whether anticipating or
delaying them in order to complete a successful action of survival that is
better adapted to the scenario in question. The emotions of longer duration
will condition those of shorter duration, in the sense that they must adjust to
the general program of action for the organism. If the emotional core is
composed by the emotion of seeking and the reproductive emotion, and the first
one has an intermittent functioning, then it must be the mammalian maternal
emotion the one that agglutinates around itself the rest of the emotional
system. In fact, the physiological maternal bond in mammals can be extended for
decades, because fetal cells cross the placental barrier and the blood-brain barrier,[2]
something which seems to indicate that the maternal emotional conditioning
occurs at an even more basic level than that of the neural systems, a fact that
would support the idea that it is this emotion the one that centralizes the mammalian
social behavior. The emotional system on the whole supposes a valuation of
third order whose objects are the valuations of the primary emotions, and
unlike the two previous valuations, the endomorphic component of the action of
response is greater, in the sense of being, relatively, less conditioned by the
environment, of requiring a less urgent validation and molding the scenario
according to the internal conditions. These three valuations, to which we could
call vital liminal valuations, or
valuations of the Unterlebenswelt, make
up the basic semantics for the actions of the organism. On them are grounded
the neocortical symbolic developments of the human being, whose valuations have
to be in harmony with these vital liminal valuations, as a kind of lower bound
which conditions them. Nihilist symbolic valuations of life have subverted the
most basic values of survival proclaiming the unreality of human existence in
favor of the unconditioned reality of a supernatural world, though -despite
negating the existence on this earth- they have transferred the world of the
emotional valuations to that ideal world, they have projected basic emotional
contents into those other worlds. Of course, it could not be otherwise, for if
it were not so, if the gods were not fathers and mothers, and the positive and
negative experiences on the other worlds were not to have an emotional content,
it would make no sense for the biological organism of the mammal.
Vital
valuations are evolutionarily previous to the higher symbolic ones and have
priority over them in their own scenarios. The neocortical control over the
subcortical systems is effective only in non-stressful situations.[3]
Emotions involve a processing of maximum efficiency of the memories of the
species in extreme situations. In these cases, the amygdala is in charge of
producing a higher quantity of dopamine and norepinephrine, interrupting the
functioning of the prefrontal cortex, in which it is located the so called
working memory or blackboard memory
-indispensable for abstract thinking-, thus being activated the emotional
protocols.[4]
The emotional neural systems are superposed with the systems that are in charge
of somatic activation, as well as with others in which are processed the
personal judgments that are adopted in decision making. These latter systems
are different from the systems that correspond to a more specific cognitive
intelligence,[5]
however, the constrictions exerted by the emotional systems over learning
during the long evolutionary periods of behavioral adaptation, have made the
emotional experience, in humans, inseparable from cognitive ones, even so in
merely logical processes.[6]
Neuro-scientific studies about deductive reasoning have shown that a process
that may seem isolated from emotions, like in the case of deduction, is conditioned
by them in neurological terms: inference is emotionally modulated.[7]
Emotions can affect deduction in two possible ways: due to the presence of
semantic content in logical reasoning, which activates the linguistic neural
systems and long term memory –which in turn activates the emotional systems-,
or directly due to the emotional content of the scene in which the reasoning
occurs, that is, the emotions of the reasoning subjects.[8]
As the experimentation undertaken by Vinod Goel has shown, the purely symbolic
reasoning, like the syllogisms in which the premises are represented by
letters, involves an activation of the visual parietal system, which is not
activated in syllogisms in which there is a semantic content. When our
propositions have a semantic content, beyond their interpretation as formal
symbols of a calculus, such semanticity resonates
emotionally in the subject, activating memories and emotions that
neuro-chemically condition the functionality of the blackboard memory,
introducing external factors into the merely formal game. The easiness by which
argumentative fallacies are produced –formal and informal- is grounded on this
phenomenon of emotional conditioning. The influence of the emotional elements
in the argumentation has been known since ancient times,[9]
and it is normally used, inadvertently or deliberately, in social
communication, even though, it was superstitiously considered that the most
formalized deductive reasoning was immune to emotional influence.
On the
other hand, as Roland Friedrich has shown using fMRI, formal and natural
reasoning are processed differently at a neural level, for they correspond to
different evolutionary areas despite their structural analogies.[10]
There are different neural processes for different reasoning actions: the deductions
of mathematical logic and those of everyday life -which are imbricated in the
mythological inheritances of the natural languages- are applied to their
corresponding scenarios, and it is not clear yet if there would be some of
these scenarios in which these neocortical activities could be harmonized with
one another. The differences between natural and formal reasoning are much
greater than it would be expected at first glance, and if we judge the patterns
of everyday life from the reasoning structures of science, we find ourselves
with a surprising abyss between them, whose explanation has the evolutionary
content that Friedrich pointed out in relation to syntax. We could speak of at
least two kinds of symbolic reasoning with their corresponding types of
valuation, although both conditioned, ultimately, by the emotional processes.
Both operate with an added mutual tension due to the inevitable interaction
that they maintain as a result of the demands of the vital processes of the
modern human being, who lives following the patterns of formal reasoning -in
which his most n-ary techniques are based-, as well as those of natural
reasoning which, being nearer to the basic emotions, serves as a link with the
praxis of such a technique in everyday life.
The
tension between these two reasoning ways is basic in order to understand modern
man psychology and the processes of emotional valuation. Let us take as a
comparative tool for natural and formal reasoning a common structure to both,
the material conditional. Bertrand Russell and the logicians characterized pure
mathematics as a class of all the propositions of the type p implies q,[11] which, aside from the validity of the declaration,
gives us an idea of the importance of the structure of the material conditional
within a field so unequivocally rational in its proceedings (not always in its
ontology). The structure of the conditional occurs in all human natural
languages,[12]
and in the last fifty years it has been as exhaustively studied by psychology
as it had been by philosophy -and in a very problematic manner- since
Aristotle.[13]
It is not my intention to treat this discussion in detail, but simply to show
what are the bases that make the material conditional such a problematic
question, in order to illustrate the difference between natural and formal
reasoning, and the place that both occupy in relation to the processes of
emotional valuation and later in myth construction.
As William
and Martha Kneale pointed out, some classical authors tried to formulate the
conditional as a necessary connection between statements, and these were
defined as constructions in which it is not possible that simultaneously the
consequent may be false (apodosis) and the antecedent true (protasis), even
though the contradictions appeared everywhere. For the Megarians Philo the
Dialectician, and his master Diodorus Cronus, well-formed conditionals cannot begin with the truth of the
antecedent and finish with the falsity of the consequent, being their
construction correct in the rest of cases of truth valuation of protasis and
apodosis. Philo argues in relation to the material conditional some questions
which even though they were left aside by the logic of the 20th Century,
appear in natural reasoning. I refer to the problematic of the temporality in
relation to antecedent and consequent, as in the case in which a conditional
may be true during a moment of the day and not so during another: If it is daytime then I am reading this
sentence. According to Philo’s framework, it would be logically true both
during the day and at night, because the falsity of the antecedent does not
make false the construction of the material conditional, but it is intuitively
contradictory. The problematic is not only due to the possible divergences
between a syntactic conditional structure and the self-referential semantic
content of a proposition, from which are derived well known paradoxes, but we
find ourselves with more general semantic problems in relation to the
conditional when the temporal dimension is introduced, a tension that occurs
between logic’s ambition of timelessness, inheritor of the Parmenidean thought
that studies the immutable essences that relate among each other in syntactic
games, and the directional mutability of experience. With an example: Let there
be P and Q two past events that are not made true simultaneously. P became factually true (in the sense
that the semantic content of the sentence P
corresponded with a set of physical actions) first, and later Q. Let us now construct the material
conditional Q→P. Such a conditional is well formed, for it never happened the
case True→False, and when afterwards it occurred True→True, it continued
to be in accordance with the definition of truth of the conditional. We are
postulating a connection between something that has not been yet, and something
that has already been.[14]
Let us suppose now that P and Q are two future events that are not
true simultaneously, and that P will
become factually false first, and later Q.
Let us now construct P→Q. The conditional is well formed, for
it would never occur True→False, and when False→True, or False→False may occur, it will be equally well formed, although we are
postulating some relations whose epistemological content is irrelevant (at
best) and paradoxical, because we are affirming a link which is non-existent
from the present point of view and that it occurs for all conditions of truth
and falsity of the antecedent and the consequent. In the case that P may become factually true first and
then Q, in order for the conditional
to be always true, we must formulate it as Q→P. On the other hand, any pair of
propositions that became true simultaneously in the past, or will become true
simultaneously in the future, will form -in any order- well-formed conditionals.
The use
of the material conditional as a necessary connection between antecedent and
consequent has not been the most common, neither in the sphere of logic nor in
ordinary thinking. In the logic after Russell, the role of the material
implication is better understood when it is considered in a wider context, like
the one provided by the axiomatic system of number theory. (x) A(x) → B(x)[15] expresses the relationship between variable
propositions, or propositional functions, that we call formal implication. The
formal conditional represents implication, not in an a priori sense, but in the
sense defined by the formal system.[16]
On the other hand, in ordinary language, the primary goal of a conditional
statement is not to maintain the notion of a necessary connection between
protasis and apodosis, but to call the attention about a possibility whose
fulfilment is somewhat uncertain to the speaker, and whose consequent has only
meaning in relation to the antecedent.[17]
This phenomenon has been studied by the psychological Mental Model Theory,[18]
which, from the syllogistic schema that takes the conditional as major premise
and as minor the affirmation or negation of the antecedent or the consequent,
has characterized ideal reasoning by means of a three-step process. The first
one involves the representation of the reasoning process through a set of
mental models compatible with the major and minor premises. In the second, a conclusion
is obtained which is innovative and true for all the models of application of
the syllogism. Lastly, counterexamples are sought for, additional models that
may be compatible with the premises but not with the conclusion.[19]
However,
in practice, the reasoning accomplished is a different one. Experimental
psychology has shown that the difficulties that formal logic has had with the
conditional since its very beginnings are rooted in our spontaneous way of thinking
the sequences of phenomena and the propositions that verbalize them. Thus, for
instance, in a syllogism in which the major premise is the conditional and the
minor Q, or ¬P, which formal logic would solve in uncertainties, are solved in
the scenarios of natural reasoning with the acceptance
of the consequent and the negation of
the antecedent.[20]
Table
1: Syllogisms of natural reasoning.
Major premise: P→Q
Name of the inferential process
|
Minor premise
|
Conclusion
|
Modus Ponens
|
P
|
Q
|
Modus Tollens
|
¬Q
|
¬P
|
Fallacy of Accepting the Consequent
|
Q
|
P
|
Fallacy of Negating the Antecedent
|
¬P
|
¬Q
|
In
natural reasoning we find two limitations with respect to formal reasoning: the
two spontaneous deviations noted (the acceptance of the consequent and the
negation of the antecedent) and the openness of the system of natural
reasoning. Both matters are related, for the deviations are partly produced due
to the confusions generated by the semantic content in relation to the
sequential content of the material conditional. If we accept the thesis that
emotions establish a proto-semantic root for symbolic communications, and that
the processes undertaken in a protocolary manner by the basic emotional systems
constitute a unity of meaning for the organism, the natural forms of inference
make sense as chains of actions (or propositions) not analyzable into
individual actions or propositions. If an stimulus (internal or external)
activates an emotional protocol E formed
by a sequence P⟹Q (read as, Q
follows necessarily from P), the synthetic unity of meaning is the pair (P, Q), that is, the protocol E, which distinguishes two temporal
irreversible moments, in which it cannot be the case that action P may occur without occurring also
action Q. If I find myself in a
dangerous situation, my organism activates the physiological changes that we
call the emotion of fear, and if the protocol is to have the effectiveness that
evolutionarily has shown, has to activate the entire sequence, so that by finding
ourselves in any of the elements of that chain of actions we can ensure that it
has been preceded by some specific actions and will be succeeded by others, as
the antecedents of the cascade progressively unfold. It is a question, then, of
a reasoning schema in which the two fallacies of accepting the consequent and
negating the antecedent make sense. The difficulty that natural reasoning has
with the acceptance of the Modus Tollens happens
because in the elements of the sequence P⟹Q, the minor premise, ¬Q, does not negate P but the synthesis of signification that forms the sequence E, which, when it occurs, has emotional
meaning, of survival, whereas when E does
not occur, we find ourselves in a natural process that corresponds to another
type of characterization, speculative and neocortical in this case, which we
could call an scenario of formal reasoning. Suppose that we construct the
following material conditional: If a
raging dog would attack you and you were near a tree that you could climb to,
it would be reasonable to climb to that tree. Let us suppose, to simplify,
that we assign to the propositional conjunction of the antecedent a single
formula P, and that we will only consider
the cases in which simultaneously occurs the attack and the fortunate presence
of the tree, or none of these two occurrences. Within a scenario of natural
reasoning, we would be dealing with a sequence E formed by P⟹Q, in which is posed a
dangerous scenario with a possible way out: the action of climbing the tree.
Suppose now that P occurs as minor
hypothesis. To conclude that Q will
occur is unproblematic, a Modus Ponens, although
if the person doing the reasoning is someone who goes usually armed, can change
the scenario and offer an alternative R:
forget the tree and kill the animal. If on the contrary, we affirm the
consequent Q, to climb the tree, the
synthetic unity of E makes us infer P (fallaciously), and in the same way,
if we negate P, we will be also
negating Q fallaciously. Natural
reasoning is occupied with elaborating scenarios with minor premises that
function as a sequence pair E(P,Q), with
a unified meaning, a unification which if it is not achieved by some of the
values of the antecedent or the consequent, it will be attained by substituting
the consequent for R, that is E’(P,R), but without touching the
antecedent, for it is the condition that defined the reasoning scenario in the
first place, and without which it makes no sense to continue thinking. Within
an emotional scenario the need for sequence is even stronger, and although the
response to fear is conditioned to the experiences of the individual in similar
stressful (liminal) situations, the initiated sequence will be completed, and
in such a context neither the minor premises like ¬P, ¬Q, make sense, nor to try to deduce the truth or falsity of P once Q has been produced, these are considerations that find their place
perfectly in reasoning processes in which the blackboard memory intervenes. The
scenarios of natural reasoning are found half way between those of emotional
liminal reasoning and those of formal liminoid reasoning. In fact, we could
consider natural reasoning as a delimitation of the processes of basic emotions
in non-urgent situations, in which n-ary emotions process sequences in a sequential
manner E(P,Q/R), which only become P⟹Q
in formalized liminoid scenarios, in which the
dominant emotion is that of knowledge (an n-ary emotion).
On the
other hand, the models of natural reasoning, as different from formal models,
are open, that is, additional information can enter the system altering the
former logical structure (called non-monotonic systems). Thus, for instance, in
relation to the myth of Oedipus, since we know that Oedipus was a man and all
men are mortal, we conclude that Oedipus died, however, knowing that later he
disappeared at the entrance of Athens, because the gods took him away, we are not so sure anymore if we could conclude his
mortality. Another similar case would be that of a friend who tells us that he
has a mammal as pet, to which he has named Fred. By having such information we
simply infer that Fred is not poisonous, but later on we find out that Fred is
a platypus, one of the rare venomous mammals, and so we change our conclusion.
The opening of natural reasoning does not only occur from the side of the
reasoning scenario, in which not all the information is determined a priori as
part of a calculus and new data can continually enter, but also from the
opening of the reasoning subject, who will interpret the scenarios following
specific mythic (ideological) structures, which condition both the formulation
of hypotheses that may be plausible with the scenarios and the rejections of
those logical assumptions that may suppose a basic contradiction with the
axiological core of its mythology. The interpretations of natural reasoning
usually lead to assign a truth-functional value to the propositions, according
to the scenarios and times in which these occur, or lead directly to accept the
paradox as a condition of some specific epistemological scenarios, especially
those that refer to exomorphic representations. However, the most complex types
of natural reasoning do not operate by a simple acceptance of the paradox, but
by means of non-monotonic adjustments.
If we observe natural reasoning, the non-monotonicity expresses itself
according to this schema: (P ∧
¬T) → (Q ∨
R), in which T represents
the adverse conditions that will impede the occurrence of Q regardless of the occurrence of P, and R represents the
additional information that enters the system. While T destroys the scenario logically, since in the Modus Ponens ¬(P ∧ ¬T) blocks the deductive
certainty, R safeguards the whole
scenario, for its acceptance as truth makes true the scenario described by the
formula, an R which can be either a
corroborated fact by social experience or a hallucinatory personal belief.[21]
With an example: If Fred is a mammal, and
not a virtual mammal, then Fred is not poisonous, or Fred is a platypus. The
proposition: Fred is a platypus, is late
information that by being thus added saves the first scenario. Another example
in which beliefs intervene: If the gods
have created the universe, then the universe is proof of our perfection in all
its actions. Here the first belief, P
(the gods have created the universe)
is expressed as a necessary condition for the whole argument, and it is not contemplated
either ¬P, or a possible T that may contradict it. The point is
to prove the consequent by means of the Modus
Ponens, and when a negation of the consequent is produced by means of a Modus Tollens, like in a proposition
that contradicts the beliefs by affirming: hunger,
war and emotional misery, in which the better part of humanity lives and which
are actions of the universe, do not show any perfection or grandeur, therefore,
the gods, if there were any, either are not perfect or have not created the
universe, the most common answer is to produce a disjunctive premise to be
added to the consequent that saves the argument: human suffering is part of a divine plan whose perfection escapes the
ordinary human, as, for example, do the Hinduism and the three religions of
the Book. In sum, the ability of human reasoning does not operate equally in
liminal scenarios than in the liminoid scenarios of experience. Formalized
thought is a late evolutionary development that is limited by the most basic
inferential operations that take place in the emotional processes. When
propositions have semantic contents, they are processed in different neural
areas than when they do not, and with the semantic content a whole valuation
system of the subject enters the scenario. For its part, the greater liminal
weight of the scenarios of natural reasoning determines absolutely the reasoning
action, and the syllogisms work spontaneously with the fallacies of accepting the consequent and negating the antecedent, moreover, such
fallacies obey a need from the part of the emotional protocols that is
perfectly intelligible. In most reasoning scenarios of human vital experience,
rationality is inseparable from emotionality.
It has
not only been proven the emotional conditioning of natural and formal
reasoning, but the alleged independence of moral judgments with respect to the
emotions (and in fact, the independence of these judgments with respect to any
human thing)[22]
-which the philosophy of ontotheological grounds was inclined to think from
Plato down to our times-, has been refuted as well by the neuro-scientific
investigations. Moral decision-making is not independent from emotions[23]
–despite the fact that both processes have a different topobiology-,[24]
that is, our morality is biologically conditioned, something that we could
simply derive from the understanding of the functionality of the emotional
protocols, but which has been also confirmed by means of neurophysiological
experimentation. Emotions condition even our perception of reality, for it has
been observed that perception data are not even processed in a simple manner,
but are re-elaborated from the combination of the emotional systems, from
criteria such as that of group cohesion (belonging and not belonging to a
particular group), something that can distort even the sizes of the objects
perceived.[25]
Some authors sustain that there is not a specific neural system for moral
judgments, but that these are produced by means of a complex interaction
between multiple neural systems which are not specific to this cognitive activity,[26]
a postulate that seems to confirm the thesis of the emotional control of
morality by proposing a decentralization of
the natural processes that correspond to moral judgments into other neural
systems. The resolution of these differences can only be empirical, even though
(regardless of there being or not an exclusive system for morality) by being an
activity that involves the emotional social neural systems, it makes no sense
to consider it independently of them. However, there is a generalized agreement
about the importance of the modulation that emotions exercise on moral
judgments, and in fact, the frontier between the emotional and the social
neuroscience is becoming increasingly vague. For this reason, human emotions
can be considered the most complex neural processes, to the extent that they
are mixed with all the other brain processes,[27]
obviously, always considering that we speak of n-ary emotions, with scenarios
of natural reasoning of the kind (P ∧ ¬T) → (Q ∨ R), dealt with earlier, and not of mere processes of
basic emotions.
N-ary emotions can perfectly handle logically
contradictory scenarios, introducing disjunctive hypotheses that express
beliefs, although they are not capable of processing scenarios that are
non-linkable to the basic emotional circuits in which the survival of the
organism is based. What is relevant to the emotion is not the form of a given
scenario, but the importance of such a scenario for the subject, its link to
any of the specific emotions that guide the actions of survival. Let us suppose
for a moment that in the future humans develop a new neural system to process
new scenarios of survival. Let us call aesthetics
to this new emotion, an emotion that we define as an exaptation of some
part of the system of rage, within an imaginary society so civilized and
reasonable that rage is already a marginal and sporadic emotion. Suppose that
the aesthetic emotion solves situations in which rage functioned before, in
such a manner that whoever has that emotion more developed will enjoy a higher
social recognition and higher reproductive opportunities, both in relation to
children and to ideas. If we are capable of imagining such emotion, is because
we associate it with the other emotional systems. If we understand this
hypothetical scenario, is because we connect it to scenarios of our current
emotional experience. An intelligent living being who may not share with us
anything more than the system of seeking, who is asexual, non-social, and who
does not feel fear or rage, would be fundamentally incomprehensible in its
actions, and it would only be comprehensible from the actions related to the
seeking neural system. Unconsciously, when we speak of intelligence we talk
about life, and when we talk about life we imply the process of development of
all or at least some of the characteristics of the emotional systems. We
consider as intelligence the adaptive ability of living beings, of which our
most formalized and methodic reasoning is but an n-ary evolutionary development
of the set of the emotive-communicative system, which functions more like a
limiting regulative condition of cognitive processes in certain liminoid
scenarios, than as a pragmatic condition of human action. The use of reason is
conditioned to the emotional homeostatic contexts of the group’s survival, and
for this reason its intervention in the narratives of identity is always
restricted by the needs of the homeostasis.
[1] Cf. Panksepp. Affective
Neuroscience. Ed. Cit. p.48.
[2] See Bianchi, D. W. et al. Male fetal progenitor cells persist in maternal blood for as long as 27
years postpartum. In Proceedings of
the National Academy of Science. U.S.A. 1996. January 23; 93(2):
p.p.705-708. Web. And also Rei Sunami et al., Migration of michrochimeric fetal cells into maternal circulation
before placenta formation. Landesbioscience.com. October, November,
December. 2010. Web.
[3] Cf. Panksepp. Affective
Neuroscience. Ed. Cit. p.301.
[4] Cf. Amy Arnsten, Carolyn M. Mazure and Rajita Sinha. El cerebro sometido a tensión. Investigación y
Ciencia. Junio 2012. Prensa Científica. Barcelona. p.p.64-67.
[5] Cf. Reuven Bar-On, et al., Exploring the Neurological Substrate of Emotional and Social
Intelligence. In Social Neuroscience.
Ed. Cit. p.p.223-235.
[6] Cf. Gerald M. Edelman. Second Nature: Brain Science and Human Knowledge. Yale University
Press. New Haven and London. 2006. p.65.
[7] See: Vinod Goel. Cognitive
Neuroscience of Reasoning. Draft Nov. 27. 2003. Web. In the book, Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and
Reasoning. Eds. K. Holyoak and R. Morrison. Cambridge University Press.
2003.
[8] Cf. Goel. Ibid. p.29.
[9] See the treatment of the enthymemes in Aristotle. Rhetoric. 1354a. 15.
[10] Cf. Roland Friedrich and Angela D. Friedrich. Mathematical
Logic in the Human Brain: Syntax. p.p. 1-5.
May 28, 2009. Plos ONE. Web.
[11] Cf. Bertrand Russell. Principles of Mathematics. W.W. Norton & Company. New York.
1964. p.3.
[12] Cf. Comrie, B. Conditionals:
A Typology. Cited in Mike Oaksford and Nick Cater (eds.). Cognition and Conditionals. Probability and Logic in Human Thinking.
Introduction. Oxford University Press. Oxford. 2010. p.3.
[13] In Sextus Empiricus, are found formulated the four
main conceptions that are developed in classical logic about the conditional. Pyrrhoneiae Hypotyposes. ii.110-112. See
the discussion of William and Martha Kneale in The Development of Logic. Oxford University Press. Oxford. 1984.
p.p.128-138.
[14] Moreover, the acceptance of the consequent in the
past carries the question of the validity of the reasoning to purely semantic
terms, to the factual truth or falsity of the statements P and Q, which no longer
belongs to formal logic.
[15] Read as: “For all x, if A is x then x is B.”
[16] Kleene, Stephen Cole. Introduction to Mathematics. North Holland Publishing Co. Amsterdam
P. Noordhoff N.V. Groningen. 1964. p.p.138.139.
[17] Kneale. Op. Cit. p.135.
[18] Started by Phillip Johnson-Laird with Mental Models: Towards a Cognitive Science
of Language, Inference and Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.
Cambridge. 1983.
[19] Sonjia M. Geiger and Klaus Oberauer. Towards a
reconciliation of mental model theory and probabilistic theories of
conditionals. In Cognition and Conditionals. Ed. Cit. p.p.295-296.
[20] This is especially noticeable in children and people
without an education in logic or mathematics. See Nilufa Ali et al. Causal discounting and conditional reasoning
in children. In Cognition and
Conditionals. Ed. Cit. p.p.117-134. And also David E. Over, Jonathan St. B.
T. Evans, and Shira Elqayam. Conditionals
and non-constructuve reasoning. In Ibid. p.p.135-151. As well as Henry
Markovits, Semantic memory retrieval,
mental models, and the development of conditional inferences in children. In
Ibid. p.p.178-195.
[21] A distinction which is not always so simple to make
when we deal with religious constructions.
[22] Analogous to the independence of mathematical objects
with respect to the ordered space-time experience to which we call world. In
moral judgments, we also deal with ideal objects whose necessity is formal
(like that of the mathematical objects) from which its universality is derived.
[23] See Joshua D. Greene. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Moral Judgment. In The Cognitive Neuroscience IV. Department
of Psychology. Harvard University. Web.
[24] A neural net which comprises the orbitofrontal
cortex, the temporal pole and the superior temporal sulcus of the left
hemisphere, is specifically activated with moral judgments, whereas evocative
emotional judgments, but not moral, activate the left amygdala, the lingual
gyrus, and the lateral orbital gyrus. (Cf. Jorge Moll et al., Functional Networks in Emotional Moral and
Nonmoral Social Judgments. In Social
Neuroscience. Op. Cit. p.63.)
[25] See, J.T. Cacioppo and Gary G. Bernston. Social Neuroscience. Ed. Cit. p.p.97-98.
[26] See, J.D. Greene, The
Cognitive Neuroscience of Moral Judgment. Ed. Cit. p.26.
[27] Cf. Gerald M. Edelman. Bright Air, Brilliant Fire. Ed. Cit. p.176.
Comments
Post a Comment
Please write here your comments